Large Sets 4
Posted by Tom Leinster
Previously: Part 3. Next: Part 5
The alephs are the succession of ever-larger infinite sets, beginning at , followed by the smallest set larger than , which is called , and then similarly , up to and beyond. At least, that’s the usual way the alephs are introduced. But in this post and the next, I’m going to come at the alephs from another angle — the opposite direction, in some sense — which is better suited to ETCS.
Last time, I promised that I’d get to the alephs this time. But in the interests of keeping each post shortish, I’m actually going to split the explanation in two. So right now, I’m going to explain something I call the “index” of a set, and next time we’ll meet the alephs themselves.
Let’s start where we left off last time: with well-orders. I mentioned that well-orders are inevitable in set theory because for any set , the set
is well-ordered by (cardinal inequality). So let’s think about more carefully.
First of all, really is a well-defined set. Any set is isomorphic to a subset of , so we can construct as a quotient of .
Category theorists generally work with non-strict inequalities, , but here I’ve used a strict inequality, . Why? Because it’s more general. If we want the set of isomorphism classes of sets , we can get it from this definition of : it’s . But there’s no set with the property that is the set of isomorphism classes of sets , because there’s no largest set .
Now, the assignment takes a set as input and produces a well-ordered set as output. We’ve already seen a different way of turning a set into a well-ordered set: the assignment , giving an initial well-order. How are and related — if at all?
For a start, they’re not the same. Suppose that is , the smallest set . Then consists of the isomorphism classes of sets , or equivalently, . These are the isomorphism classes of finite sets together with the isomorphism class of itself:
So is a countable well-ordered set. On the other hand, is the uncountable set equipped with a certain well-order. So .
But and are related. Indeed, one can show that
for all . In words: there are at most as many cardinalities smaller than as there are elements of . We’ll use this fact another day.
At this point I’m going to do a harmless but unmotivated little sidestep, in order to conform with a certain custom in set theory (which we’ll meet next time). I don’t know of any way to justify it except tradition, though maybe someone will fill me in. Anyway, it’s this: we’re going to shift focus from the set of iso classes of all sets to the set of iso classes of infinite sets X. I’ll call this the index of :
For example, is the 3-element well-ordered set, the elements being the isomorphism classes of , and . The index of a finite set is empty, so when I’m talking about indices, I’ll always assume it’s an infinite set we’re dealing with.
I just made up the word “index”.
Question Do set theorists have a standard name for “index”?
For reasons I’ll explain next time, I wouldn’t be surprised if they don’t. But if they do, I’d like to know it.
There’s a picture in my head:
This is what could be called the tautological bundle associated with . The elements of are the isomorphism classes of infinite sets , and this “bundle” consists of a set and a function
such that the fibre over is itself. (You can construct as a subset of .) So each infinite set appears as a fibre exactly once. If maps into are viewed as families indexed by , then in slightly loose notation, this family is
Indices have some good properties. For example,
The on the left-hand side means successor set, a construction I explained before and have already been using in this post. But the on the right-hand side is the successor well-ordered set, which I haven’t mentioned before. It’s the construction that takes a well-ordered set and produces a new one, , consisting of with a new greatest element adjoined (even if already has one). It’s the smallest well-ordered set .
In fact, for infinite sets ,
A well-ordered set that is not a successor is called a limit, and a set that is not a successor is a weak limit. So another way to say this is:
But the most important property of the index is this: for infinite sets and ,
In particular, the process of taking the index is injective (up to isomorphism):
So, writing for the collection of infinite sets, Index is an order embedding
There’s now an obvious question: what is the image of this embedding? That is:
Which well-ordered sets are the index of some set?
Certainly is: it’s the index of . And since , if is the index of something then so is . It’s also not too hard to see that if is the index of something then so is every well-ordered set . So the collection of well-ordered sets arising as indices is nonempty, closed under taking successors, and downwards closed.
But in ETCS, not every well-ordered set has to be the index of something. Indeed:
It is consistent with ETCS that there is no set with index .
For we saw above that since the well-ordered set is a limit, any set with index must be a weak limit. It must also be uncountable. And in part 2, we saw that it’s consistent with ETCS that there are no uncountable weak limits.
So the picture is this. In a model of ETCS, either all well-ordered sets arise as indices, or those below some threshold do and those above the threshold don’t.
We might therefore consider adding the following axiom to ETCS:
Every well-ordered set is the index of some set.
This axiom can be rephrased in several equivalent ways, as follows.
Take a model of ETCS, and suppose it satisfies this axiom. Let be a well-ordered set. Then is the index of some set , and the “tautological bundle” of consists of a set and a function with the following property:
for each , the fibre is the smallest infinite set for each .
Let’s say that a model of ETCS is Cantorian if every well-ordered set admits a map into it with this property. So, we’ve just shown that “every well-ordered set is an index” implies Cantorian.
The converse is also true… but isn’t quite obvious.
Let me explain briefly how the proof goes. We’ve got a well-ordered set and we’re trying to show that it’s the index of some set . How can we lay our hands on such an ?
Well, we’re given that there’s a map into whose fibres are the infinite sets up to a certain threshold. But none of them is quite as big as : they stop one short. For example, if then the above has fibres , and . But is the index of , so this isn’t quite enough.
What we actually have to do is apply the Cantorian axiom to . This gives a map with the property above, and it’s the top fibre — the fibre over the isomorphism class of itself — that gives us the desired set , of which is the index.
So for models of ETCS,
(every well-ordered set is the index of some set) Cantorian.
There’s yet another equivalent way of stating this condition, which has the virtue of being entirely about sets, not ordered sets:
For every set , there exists a function into whose fibres are pairwise non-isomorphic.
In other words, for every set , there exist a set and a function such that is not isomorphic to for in . This is clearly implied by the Cantorian axiom: just well-order arbitrarily. But a little argument shows that in fact, it’s equivalent.
Next time
We’ve seen that the process of taking the index defines a bijection from
isomorphism classes of infinite sets
to
isomorphims classes of well-ordered sets that are the index of something.
Next time, we’ll look at the inverse process, mapping a well-ordered set to the set of which it is the index (if there is one). This inverse is written as — and these are the promised alephs.
Re: Large Sets 4
I’m enjoying this series. Could you write something about references? Presumably some of this category-theoretic approach to large sets is covered in papers or books somewhere and some of it is not and you are discovering this presentation for yourself.